Results for 'Lynton Keith Caldwell'

961 found
Order:
  1.  9
    Review of Caldwell, Lynton Keith, Shrader-Frechette, Kristen, Policy for Land: Law and Ethics. [REVIEW]Dan T. Vadnjal - 1997 - Environmental Values 6 (3):365-366.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Human limitations and the future of technology.Lynton K. Caldwell - 1978 - Humanitas 14:47.
  3.  8
    Engineering and Ecodevelopment: International Initiatives.Lynton K. Caldwell - 1981 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 1 (4):327-338.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Wisdom and Responsibility. By Arthur Child. [REVIEW]Lynton K. Caldwell - 1946 - Ethics 57:147.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  14
    Course Syllabus: Biology and Politics.Robert V. Bartlett & Lynton K. Caldwell - 1981 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 1 (4):423-425.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  16
    Science, Technology, and Public Policy.Robert V. Bartlett & Lynton K. Caldwell - 1981 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 1 (1-2):215-221.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  24
    Abnormal frontostriatal activity in recently abstinent cocaine users during implicit moral processing.Brendan M. Caldwell, Carla L. Harenski, Keith A. Harenski, Samantha J. Fede, Vaughn R. Steele, Michael R. Koenigs & Kent A. Kiehl - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9:155442.
    Investigations into the neurobiology of moral cognition are often done by examining clinical populations characterized by diminished moral emotions and a proclivity toward immoral behavior. Psychopathy is the most common disorder studied for this purpose. Although cocaine abuse is highly co-morbid with psychopathy and cocaine-dependent individuals exhibit many of the same abnormalities in socio-affective processing as psychopaths, this population has received relatively little attention in moral psychology. To address this issue, the authors used functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) to record (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  45
    Review of Lynton K. Caldwell: The Administrative Theories of Hamilton and Jefferson: Their Contribution to Thought on Public Administration[REVIEW]John A. Vieg - 1947 - Ethics 57 (2):147-148.
  9. Proper names and identifying descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):335 - 358.
  10.  96
    Mind and Supermind.Keith Frankish - 2004 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Mind and Supermind offers an alternative perspective on the nature of belief and the structure of the human mind. Keith Frankish argues that the folk-psychological term 'belief' refers to two distinct types of mental state, which have different properties and support different kinds of mental explanation. Building on this claim, he develops a picture of the human mind as a two-level structure, consisting of a basic mind and a supermind, and shows how the resulting account sheds light on a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  11.  41
    The Case for Investment Advising as a Virtue-Based Practice.Keith D. Wyma - 2015 - Journal of Business Ethics 127 (1):231-249.
    Contemporary virtue ethics was revolutionized by Alasdair MacIntyre’s reconfiguration using practices as the starting point for understanding virtues. However, MacIntyre has very pointedly excluded the professions of the financial world from the reformulation. He does not count these professions as practices, and further charges that virtue would actually hinder or even rule out one’s pursuit of these professions. This paper addresses three tasks, in regard to the financial profession of investment advising. First, the paper lays out MacIntyre’s soon-to-be-published charges against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  12. Now you know it, now you don’t.Keith DeRose - 2000 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5:91-106.
    Resistance to contextualism comes in the form of many very different types of objections. My topic here is a certain group or family of related objections to contextualism that I call “Now you know it, now you don’t” objections. I responded to some such objections in my “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions” a few years back. In what follows here, I will expand on that earlier response in various ways, and, in doing so, I will discuss some aspects of David Lewis’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  13. “Bamboozled by Our Own Words”: Semantic Blindness and Some Arguments Against Contextualism.Keith Derose - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2):316 - 338.
    The best grounds for accepting contextualism concerning knowledge attributions are to be found in how knowledge-attributing (and knowledge-denying) sentences are used in ordinary, nonphilosophical talk: What ordinary speakers will count as “knowledge” in some non-philosophical contexts they will deny is such in others. Contextualists typically appeal to pairs of cases that forcefully display the variability in the epistemic standards that govern ordinary usage: A “low standards” case (henceforth, “LOW”) in which a speaker seems quite appropriately and truthfully to ascribe knowledge (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  14. Plurals and complexes.Keith Hossack - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (3):411-443.
    Atomism denies that complexes exist. Common-sense metaphysics may posit masses, composite individuals and sets, but atomism says there are only simples. In a singularist logic, it is difficult to make a plausible case for atomism. But we should accept plural logic, and then atomism can paraphrase away apparent reference to complexes. The paraphrases require unfamiliar plural universals, but these are of independent interest; for example, we can identify numbers and sets with plural universals. The atomist paraphrases would fail if plurals (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  15. Descartes, epistemic principles, epistemic circularity, and scientia.Keith DeRose - 1992 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73 (3):220-238.
  16.  57
    Truth, Evidence, and Inference.Keith Lehrer - 1974 - American Philosophical Quarterly 11 (2):79 - 92.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  10
    Determinism and Human Choice.Keith Lehrer - 1974 - Proceedings of the XVth World Congress of Philosophy 4:79-83.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Evaluation and consciousness.Keith Lehrer - 1997 - In Self-trust: a study of reason, knowledge, and autonomy. New York: Oxford University Press.
  19. Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic?Keith Hutchison - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):307-323.
  20. Reference and paradox.Keith Simmons - 2003 - In J. C. Beall (ed.), Liars and Heaps: New Essays on Paradox. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 230--252.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  26
    Interpretation, representation, and deductive reasoning.Keith Stenning & Michiel van Lambalgen - 2008 - In Jonathan Eric Adler & Lance J. Rips (eds.), Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 223-248.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  40
    The IRB paradox: Could the protectors also encourage deceit?Patricia Keith-Spiegel & Gerald P. Koocher - 2005 - Ethics and Behavior 15 (4):339 – 349.
    The efforts of some institutional review boards (IRBs) to exercise what is viewed as appropriate oversight may contribute to deceit on the part of investigators who feel unjustly treated. An organizational justice paradigm provides a useful context for exploring why certain IRB behaviors may lead investigators to believe that they have not received fair treatment. These feelings may, in turn, lead to intentional deception by investigators that IRBs will rarely detect. Paradoxically, excessive protective zeal by IRBs may actually encourage misconduct (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  23. Charles Taylor: Modernity, Freedom and Community.Keith Spence - 2003 - University of Wales Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    Bilateralism and Community in Treaty Law and Practice–From Warriors, Workers and (Hook-) Worms.Kenneth J. Keith - 2011 - In Ulrich Fastenrath, Rudolf Geiger, Daniel-Erasmus Khan, Andreas Paulus, Sabine von Schorlemer & Christoph Vedder (eds.), From Bilateralism to Community Interest: Essays in Honour of Judge Bruno Simma. Oxford University Press. pp. 754--767.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  26
    God and Propositions.Keith Yandell - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (2):275-287.
    If there are abstract objects, they necessarily exist. The majority view among contemporary philosophers of religion who are theists is that God also necessarily exists. Nonetheless, that God has necessary existence has not been shown to be true, or even (informally) consistent. It seems consistent—at least is does not seem (informally) inconsistent—but neither does its denial. Arguments that necessary existence is a perfection, and God has all perfections, assume that Necessitarian Theism is true, and hence consistent. Thus they do not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  38
    A Gross and Palpable Contradiction?: Incarnation and Consistency.Keith E. Yandell - 1994 - Sophia 33 (3):30 - 45.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  40
    Theism and evil: A reply.Keith E. Yandell - 1972 - Sophia 11 (1):1-7.
  28.  31
    Inventing the French Revolution: Essays on French Political Culture in the Eighteenth Century.Keith Michael Baker - 1990 - Cambridge University Press.
    How did the French Revolution become thinkable? Keith Michael Baker, a leading authority on the ideological origins of the French Revolution, explores this question in his wide-ranging collection of essays. Analyzing the new politics of contestation that transformed the traditional political culture of the Old Regime during its last decades, Baker revises our historical map of the political space in which the French Revolution took form. Some essays study the ways in which the revolutionaries' break with the past was (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. Induction, reason and consistency.Keith Lehrer - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):103-114.
  30. Is Kuhn a sociologist?Keith Jones - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (4):443-452.
  31. Believing in Miracles.Keith Ward - 2002 - Zygon 37 (3):741-750.
    David Hume’s arguments against believing reports of miracles are shown to be very weak. Laws of nature, I suggest, are best seen not as exceptionless rules but as context-dependent realizations of natural powers. In that context miracles transcend the natural order not as "violations" but as intelligible realizations of a divine supernatural purpose. Miracles are not parts of scientific theory but can be parts of a web of rational belief fully consistent with science. (edited).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32.  38
    Ethics, evils and theism.Keith E. Yandell - 1969 - Sophia 8 (2):18-28.
  33. Externalism and skepticism.Keith DeRose - manuscript
    A few years back, I participated in the Spindell Conference in Memphis, and gave a paper, “How Can We Know That We’re Not Brains in Vats?” (available on-line at: http://pantheon.yale.edu/~kd47/Spindell.htm). The bulk of that paper concerned responses to skepticism. I pursued an unusually radical criticism of the often-criticized “Putnam-style” responses to skepticism. To put it rather enigmatically, I argued that such responses don’t work even if they work! And I compared such responses with the type of response I favor – (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  95
    Is religion dangerous?Keith Ward - 2006 - Grand Rapids, Mich.: William B. Eerdmans Pub. Co..
    The causes of violence -- The corruptibility of all things human -- Religion and war -- Faith and reason -- Life after death -- Morality and the Bible -- Morality and faith -- The enlightenment, liberal thought and religion -- Does religion do more harm than good in personal life? -- What good has religion done?
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  6
    Before the luddites. Custom, community and machinery in the English woollen industry, 1776–1809.Keith Wrightson - 1994 - History of European Ideas 18 (2):298-299.
  36.  22
    The Nature of a Practice’s Goods.Keith Wyma - 2019 - Business Ethics Journal Review 7 (5):27-33.
    Daniel Sportiello argues that my support of financial planning as a MacIntyrean practice fails because I have misunderstood the concept of internal goods, and because financial planning then has no internal good at all. Here, I rebut those charges.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  17
    11. Divine Necessity and Divine Goodness.Keith E. Yandell - 1988 - In Thomas V. Morris (ed.), Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. pp. 313-344.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  22
    Empiricism and theism.Keith Yandell - 1968 - Sophia 7 (3):3-11.
  39.  15
    Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God.Keith E. Yandell - 2002 - Philosophia Christi 4 (2):539-541.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  54
    On interpreting the "bhagavadgītā".Keith E. Yandell - 1982 - Philosophy East and West 32 (1):37-46.
  41.  22
    Reply to Nielsen.Keith Yandell - 1968 - Sophia 7 (3):18-19.
  42.  44
    Some reflections on Indian metaphysics.Keith E. Yandell - 2001 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 50 (1/3):171-190.
  43.  61
    Tragedy and evil.Keith E. Yandell - 1994 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 36 (1):1 - 26.
  44.  42
    The Non-Epistemic Explanation of Religious Belief.Keith E. Yandell - 1990 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 27 (1/2):87 - 120.
    The preceding two sections have considered, respectively, the discreditation of psychological belief, and of propositional belief, which begins with the claim that a belief possessed by some person is non-epistemically explicable and ends with the claim that that person is unreasonable or that that belief is (probably) false. Obviously, only certain strategies of discreditation were discussed, and those only partially. But if the examples of discrediting strategies were representative, and the remarks made about them were correct, what, if anything, follows?It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  71
    Non-monotonic inference.Keith Frankish - 2005 - In Keith Brown (ed.), Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. Elsevier.
    In most logical systems, inferences cannot be invalidated simply by the addition of new premises. If an inference can be drawn from a set of premises S, then it can also be drawn from any larger set incorporrating S. The truth of the original premises guarantees the truth of the inferred conclusion, and the addition of extra premises cannot undermine it. This property is known as monotonicity. Nonmonotonic inference lacks this property. The conclusions drawn are provisional, and new information may (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. Higher-order preferences and the master rationality motive.Keith E. Stanovich - 2008 - Thinking and Reasoning 14 (1):111 – 127.
    The cognitive critique of the goals and desires that are input into the implicit calculations that result in instrumental rationality is one aspect of what has been termed broad rationality (Elster, 1983). This cognitive critique involves, among other things, the search for rational integration (Nozick, 1993)—that is, consistency between first-order and second-order preferences. Forming a second-order preference involves metarepresentational abilities made possible by mental decoupling operations. However, these decoupling abilities are separable from the motive that initiates the cognitive critique itself. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  87
    Aquinas on Attachment, Envy, and Hatred in the "Summa Theologica".Keith Green - 2007 - Journal of Religious Ethics 35 (3):403 - 428.
    This essay examines Aquinas's discussions of hatred in Summa Theologica I-II, Q. 29 and II-II, Q. 34, in order to retrieve an account of what contemporary theorists of the emotions call its cognitive contents. In Aquinas's view, hatred is constituted as a passion by a narrative pattern that includes its intentional object, beliefs, perceptions of changes in bodily states, and motivated desires. This essay endorses Aquinas's broadly "cognitivist" account of passional hatred, in line with his way of treating passions in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  48.  86
    Paths in Zygmunt Bauman's Social Thought.Keith Tester - 2002 - Thesis Eleven 70 (1):55-71.
    This article seeks to explore some of the origins of Zygmunt Bauman's social thought. Using the metaphor of paths from a story by Borges, the article argues that Bauman's work follows paths which were opened up to him by Gramsci, Camus and Levinas. Bauman has acknowledged the importance of Gramsci and Levinas in his intellectual development and, therefore, the identification of a path leading from Camus is offered by way of circumstantial rather than direct evidence. The article discusses each of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  61
    Not So Trifling Nuances: Pierre Bourdieu, Symbolic Violence, and the Perversions of Democracy.Keith Topper - 2001 - Constellations 8 (1):30-56.
  50. Agonism, antagonism and the necessity of care.Keith Breen - 2008 - In Andrew Schaap (ed.), Law and Agonistic Politics. Ashgate Pub. Company.
1 — 50 / 961